Starting to think about AI Fairness
The topic of AI fairness metrics is as important to society as it is confusing. Confusing it is due to a number of reasons: terminological proliferation, abundance of formulae, and last not least the impression that everyone else seems to know what they’re talking about. This text hopes to counteract some of that confusion by starting from a common-sense approach of contrasting two basic positions: On the one hand, the assumption that dataset features may be taken as reflecting the underlying concepts ML practitioners are interested in; on the other, that there inevitably is a gap between concept and measurement, a gap that may be bigger or smaller depending on what is being measured. In contrasting these fundamental views, we bring together concepts from ML, legal science, and political philosophy.
If you use deep learning for unsupervised part-of-speech tagging of Sanskrit, or knowledge discovery in physics, you probably don’t need to worry about model fairness. If you’re a data scientist working at a place where decisions are made about people, however, or an academic researching models that will be used to such ends, chances are that you’ve already been thinking about this topic. — Or feeling that you should. And thinking about this is hard.
It is hard for several reasons. In this text, I will go into just one.
The forest for the trees
Nowadays, it is hard to find a modeling framework that does not include functionality to assess fairness. (Or is at least planning to.) And the terminology sounds so familiar, as well: “calibration”, “predictive parity”, “equal true [false] positive rate”… It almost seems as though we could just take the metrics we make use of anyway (recall or precision, say), test for equality across groups, and that’s it. Let’s assume, for a second, it really was that simple. Then the question still is: Which metrics, exactly, do we choose?
In reality things are not simple. And it gets worse. For very good reasons, there is a close connection in the ML fairness literature to concepts that are primarily treated in other disciplines, such as the legal sciences: discrimination and disparate impact (both not being far from yet another statistical concept, statistical parity). Statistical parity means that if we have a classifier, say to decide whom to hire, it should result in as many applicants from the disadvantaged group (e.g., Black people) being hired as from the advantaged one(s). But that is quite a different requirement from, say, equal true/false positive rates!
So despite all that abundance of software, guides, and decision trees, even: This is not a simple, technical decision. It is, in fact, a technical decision only to a small degree.
Common sense, not math
Let me start this section with a disclaimer: Most of the sources referenced in this text appear, or are implied on the “Guidance” page of IBM’s framework AI Fairness 360. If you read that page, and everything that’s said and not said there appears clear from the outset, then you may not need this more verbose exposition. If not, I invite you to read on.
Papers on fairness in machine learning, as is common in fields like computer science, abound with formulae. Even the papers referenced here, though selected not for their theorems and proofs but for the ideas they harbor, are no exception. But to start thinking about fairness as it might apply to an ML process at hand, common language – and common sense – will do just fine. If, after analyzing your use case, you judge that the more technical results are relevant to the process in question, you will find that their verbal characterizations will often suffice. It is only when you doubt their correctness that you will need to work through the proofs.
At this point, you may be wondering what it is I am contrasting those “more technical results” with. This is the topic of the next section, where I’ll try to give a birds-eye characterization of fairness criteria and what they imply.
Situating fairness criteria
Think back to the example of a hiring algorithm. What does it mean for this algorithm to be fair? We approach this question under two – incompatible, mostly – assumptions:
The algorithm is fair if it behaves the same way independent of which demographic group it is applied to. Here demographic group could be defined by ethnicity, gender, abledness, or in fact any categorization suggested by the context.
The algorithm is fair if it does not discriminate against any demographic group.
I’ll call these the technical and societal views, respectively.
Fairness, viewed the technical way
What does it mean for an algorithm to “behave the same way” regardless of which group it is applied to?
In a classification setting, we can view the relationship between prediction ($\hat{Y}$) and target ($Y$) as a doubly directed path. In one direction: Given true target $Y$, how accurate is prediction $\hat{Y}$? In the other: Given $\hat{Y}$, how well does it predict the true class $Y$?
Based on the direction they operate in, metrics popular in machine learning overall can be split into two categories. In the first, starting from the true target, we have recall, together with “the rates”: true positive, true negative, false positive, false negative. In the second, we have precision, together with positive (negative, resp.) predictive value.
If now we demand that these metrics be the same across groups, we arrive at corresponding fairness criteria: equal false positive rate, equal positive predictive value, etc. In the inter-group setting, the two types of metrics may be arranged under headings “equality of opportunity” and “predictive parity”. You’ll encounter these as actual headers in the summary table at the end of this text. (Said table organizes concepts from different areas into a three-category format. The overall narrative builds up towards that “map” in a bottom-up way – meaning, most entries will not make sense at this point.}
While overall, the terminology around metrics can be confusing (to me it is), these headings have some mnemonic value. Equality of opportunity suggests that people similar in real life ($Y$) get classified similarly ($\hat{Y}$). Predictive parity suggests that people classified similarly ($\hat{Y}$) are, in fact, similar ($Y$).
The two criteria can concisely be characterized using the language of statistical independence. Following Barocas et al., these are:
Separation: Given true target $Y$, prediction $\hat{Y}$ is independent of group membership ($\hat{Y} \perp A | Y$).
Sufficiency: Given prediction $\hat{Y}$, target $Y$ is independent of group membership ($Y \perp A | \hat{Y}$).
Given those two fairness criteria – and two sets of corresponding metrics – the natural question arises: Can we satisfy both? Above, I was mentioning precision and recall on purpose: to maybe “prime” you to think in the direction of “precision-recall trade-off”. And really, these two categories reflect different preferences; usually, it is impossible to optimize for both. The most famous, probably, result is due to Chouldechova : It says that predictive parity (testing for sufficiency) is incompatible with error rate balance (separation) when prevalence differs across groups. This is a theorem (yes, we’re in the realm of theorems and proofs here) that may not be surprising, in light of Bayes’ theorem, but is of great practical importance nonetheless: Unequal prevalence usually is the norm, not the exception.
This necessarily means we have to make a choice. And this is where the theorems and proofs do matter. For example, Heidari et al. show that in this framework – the strictly technical approach to fairness – separation should be preferred over sufficiency, because the latter allows for arbitrary disparity amplification. Thus, in this framework, we may have to work through the theorems.
What is the alternative?
Fairness, viewed as a social construct
Starting with what I just wrote: No one will likely challenge fairness being a social construct. But what does that entail?
Let me start with a biographical reminiscence. In undergraduate psychology (a long time ago), probably the most hammered-in distinction relevant to experiment planning was that between a hypothesis and its operationalization. The hypothesis is what you want to substantiate, conceptually; the operationalization is what you measure. There necessarily can’t be a one-to-one correspondence; we’re just striving to implement the best operationalization possible.
In the world of datasets and algorithms, all we have are measurements. And often, these are treated as though they were the concepts. This will get more concrete with an example, and we’ll stay with the hiring software scenario.
Assume the dataset used for training, assembled from scoring previous employees, contains a set of predictors (among which, high-school grades) and a target variable, say an indicator whether an employee did “survive” probation. There is a concept-measurement mismatch on both sides.
For one, say the grades are intended to reflect ability to learn, and motivation to learn. But depending on the circumstances, there are influence factors of much higher impact: socioeconomic status, constantly having to struggle with prejudice, overt discrimination, and more.
And then, the target variable. If the thing it’s supposed to measure is “was hired for seemed like a good fit, and was retained since was a good fit”, then all is good. But normally, HR departments are aiming for more than just a strategy of “keep doing what we’ve always been doing”.
Unfortunately, that concept-measurement mismatch is even more fatal, and even less talked about, when it’s about the target and not the predictors. (Not accidentally, we also call the target the “ground truth”.) An infamous example is recidivism prediction, where what we really want to measure – whether someone did, in fact, commit a crime – is replaced, for measurability reasons, by whether they were convicted. These are not the same: Conviction depends on more then what someone has done – for instance, if they’ve been under intense scrutiny from the outset.
Fortunately, though, the mismatch is clearly pronounced in the AI fairness literature. Friedler et al. distinguish between the construct and observed spaces; depending on whether a near-perfect mapping is assumed between these, they talk about two “worldviews”: “We’re all equal” (WAE) vs. “What you see is what you get” (WYSIWIG). If we’re all equal, membership in a societally disadvantaged group should not – in fact, may not – affect classification. In the hiring scenario, any algorithm employed thus has to result in the same proportion of applicants being hired, regardless of which demographic group they belong to. If “What you see is what you get”, we don’t question that the “ground truth” is the truth.
This talk of worldviews may seem unnecessary philosophical, but the authors go on and clarify: All that matters, in the end, is whether the data is seen as reflecting reality in a naïve, take-at-face-value way.
For example, we might be ready to concede that there could be small, albeit uninteresting effect-size-wise, statistical differences between men and women as to spatial vs. linguistic abilities, respectively. We know for sure, though, that there are much greater effects of socialization, starting in the core family and reinforced, progressively, as adolescents go through the education system. We therefore apply WAE, trying to (partly) compensate for historical injustice. This way, we’re effectively applying affirmative action, defined as
A set of procedures designed to eliminate unlawful discrimination among applicants, remedy the results of such prior discrimination, and prevent such discrimination in the future.
In the already-mentioned summary table, you’ll find the WYSIWIG principle mapped to both equal opportunity and predictive parity metrics. WAE maps to the third category, one we haven’t dwelled upon yet: demographic parity, also known as statistical parity. In line with what was said before, the requirement here is for each group to be present in the positive-outcome class in proportion to its representation in the input sample. For example, if thirty percent of applicants are Black, then at least thirty percent of people selected should be Black, as well. A term commonly used for cases where this does not happen is disparate impact: The algorithm affects different groups in different ways.
Similar in spirit to demographic parity, but possibly leading to different outcomes in practice, is conditional demographic parity. Here we additionally take into account other predictors in the dataset; to be precise: all other predictors. The desiderate now is that for any choice of attributes, outcome proportions should be equal, given the protected attribute and the other attributes in question. I’ll come back to why this may sound better in theory than work in practice in the next section.
Summing up, we’ve seen commonly used fairness metrics organized into three groups, two of which share a common assumption: that the data used for training can be taken at face value. The other starts from the outside, contemplating what historical events, and what political and societal factors have made the given data look as they do.
Before we conclude, I’d like to try a quick glance at other disciplines, beyond machine learning and computer science, domains where fairness figures among the central topics. This section is necessarily limited in every respect; it should be seen as a flashlight, an invitation to read and reflect rather than an orderly exposition. The short section will end with a word of caution: Since drawing analogies can feel highly enlightening (and is intellectually satisfying, for sure), it is easy to abstract away practical realities. But I’m getting ahead of myself.
A quick glance at neighboring fields: law and political philosophy
In jurisprudence, fairness and discrimination constitute an important subject. A recent paper that caught my attention is Wachter et al. 2020 . From a machine learning perspective, the interesting point is the classification of metrics into bias-preserving and bias-transforming. The terms speak for themselves: Metrics in the first group reflect biases in the dataset used for training; ones in the second do not. In that way, the distinction parallels Friedler et al.‘s confrontation of two “worldviews”. But the exact words used also hint at how guidance by metrics feeds back into society: Seen as strategies, one preserves existing biases; the other, to consequences unknown a priori, changes the world.
To the ML practitioner, this framing is of great help in evaluating what criteria to apply in a project. Helpful, too, is the systematic mapping provided of metrics to the two groups; it is here that, as alluded to above, we encounter conditional demographic parity among the bias-transforming ones. I agree that in spirit, this metric can be seen as bias-transforming; if we take two sets of people who, per all available criteria, are equally qualified for a job, and then find the whites favored over the Blacks, fairness is clearly violated. But the problem here is “available”: per all available criteria. What if we have reason to assume that, in a dataset, all predictors are biased? Then it will be very hard to prove that discrimination has occurred.
A similar problem, I think, surfaces when we look at the field of political philosophy, and consult theories on distributive justice for guidance. Heidari et al. have written a paper comparing the three criteria – demographic parity, equality of opportunity, and predictive parity – to egalitarianism, equality of opportunity (EOP) in the Rawlsian sense, and EOP seen through the glass of luck egalitarianism, respectively. While the analogy is fascinating, it too assumes that we may take what is in the data at face value. In their likening predictive parity to luck egalitarianism, they have to go to especially great lengths, in assuming that the predicted class reflects effort exerted. In the below table, I therefore take the liberty to disagree, and map a libertarian view of distributive justice to both equality of opportunity and predictive parity metrics.
In summary, we end up with two highly controversial categories of fairness criteria, one bias-preserving, “what you see is what you get”-assuming, and libertarian, the other bias-transforming, “we’re all equal”-thinking, and egalitarian. Here, then, is that often-announced table.
Demographic parity | Equality of opportunity | Predictive parity | |
---|---|---|---|
A.K.A. / subsumes / related concepts | statistical parity, group fairness, disparate impact, conditional demographic parity | equalized odds, equal false positive / negative rates | equal positive / negative predictive values, calibration by group |
Statistical independence criterion | independence | separation | sufficiency) |
Individual / group | group | group (most) or individual (fairness through awareness) | group |
Distributive Justice | egalitarian | libertarian (contra Heidari et al., see above) | libertarian (contra Heidari et al., see above) |
Effect on bias | transforming | preserving | preserving |
Policy / “worldview” | We’re all equal (WAE) | What you see is what you get (WYSIWIG) | What you see is what you get (WYSIWIG) |
(A) Conclusion
In line with its original goal – to provide some help in starting to think about AI fairness metrics – this article does not end with recommendations. It does, however, end with an observation. As the last section has shown, amidst all theorems and theories, all proofs and memes, it makes sense to not lose sight of the concrete: the data trained on, and the ML process as a whole. Fairness is not something to be evaluated post hoc; the feasibility of fairness is to be reflected on right from the beginning.
In that regard, assessing impact on fairness is not that different from that essential, but often toilsome and non-beloved, stage of modeling that precedes the modeling itself: exploratory data analysis.
Thanks for reading!
Photo by Anders Jildén on Unsplash